The Role of Symbiosis in Evolutionary Adaptation

Richard A. Watson

This page outlines my understanding (so far) of the mechanisms and concepts involved in symbiosis and its role in evolutionary adaptation. Although these ideas provide the motivation for my thesis work, my published work to date is necessarily more conservative. The final section below discusses how my papers relate to the ideas I discuss.

 The facts from nature
 Units of selection
 Fuzzy units-of-selection
 Research directions
 References

The facts from nature

The phrase "survival of the fittest", ubiquitous in our thoughts about evolution, is often taken to mean mutually exclusive competition. Accordingly, mutually beneficial relationships are generally treated as a curio. But biological evidence suggests that symbiosis is an important enabling mechanism in evolutionary innovation.

In its strongest form, symbiosis can lead to symbiogenesis: the genesis of new species via the genetic integration of symbionts [Merezhkovsky 1909]:

"...different bacteria form consortia that, under ecological pressures, associate and undergo metabolic and genetic change such that their tightly integrated communities result in individuality at a more complex level of organization." [Margulis, 1995].
For example, eukaryotes, which include all plants and animals, have a symbiogenic origin. A more general but closely related phenomenon characterises other "major transitions in evolution":
"entities that were capable of independent replication before the transition can replicate only as part of a larger whole after it." [Maynard-Smith & Szathmary, 1995].
However, despite the recognition of symbiosis in the natural history of evolution, there is very little understanding about how it can be formalised and integrated into evolutionary theory. The combination of pre-adapted parts into a new whole is a fundementally different source of innovation from the Darwinian view - i.e. gradual accumulation of 'blind' mutations/variations. Of course, the development of symbiotic groups and their role in evolution all occurs within the framework of natural selection: heritable variation and differential reproduction. But, symbiogenesis provides a very different source of variation from random mutations, and the biological facts about the origin of innovation in evolution suggest that mutualism, as well as competition, may play an important role in providing the advantage under selection.
 

Units of selection

In trying to understand how differential reproduction can mean anything other than competition we need to acknowledge different units-of-selection. At some level it is competition that drives selection. Differential reproduction means that some survive and some dont - I cant think of another way to interpret this except as competition. But what survives? What are the units of selection? Specifically, if we talk about selection acting on symbiotic groups - that is, selecting between alternate groups - then it will not be surprising to find mutualism within the group. Cooperation within the group is driven by the competition between groups.

Although this point of view may seem natural and straight forward it opens up a whole can of worms. The whole "group selection" debate has been a messy one - with very strong opinions on both sides. As I understand it, it used to be fashionable to talk about selection at whatever level makes a good story: sometimes it might be the individual level, sometimes it might be the family level, often it might be the species level, or anything upto the kingdom - plants vs animals. Quite rightly, this was criticised harshly. It transpired that nearly all of the adaptations observed in nature that were previously explained using higher levels of selection - 'for the good of the species' - could be explained using individual selection if you cared to look a little more closely.

Subsequently, 'group selection' has become a tabu subject, and the field has been left, for the most part, with the position that 'group selection does not exist; selection at the individual level is the only mechanism in evolution and is sufficient to explain all adaptations'. Some go further, Richard Dawkins, for example, will tell you that the correct unit-of-selection is the gene and that selection at this level is sufficient to explain everything. But thats another story.

In light of this background from the group selection debate it is very hard to even discuss selection at any higher level these days. Any mention of adaptive mutualism is often interpreted as ignorant sentimentalism. The prefered explanation for observed mutualism is either that it is merely an abberation (on the otherwise relentless path of mutually exclusive competition), or if treated seriously at all, it is 'explained away' by reducing the interactions involved to the individual level and showing that each individual is merely acting in its own self-interest. Well duh! What did you expect? Perhaps you expected bacteria, for example, that were acting for the good of the group out of the kindness of their hearts?

Are they doing it out of the kindness of their hearts? - No. Are they doing it? - Yes.

The prevailing position is that it is selfish individualism (hence, The Selfish Gene) that drives everything. But this language is just as emotive as the group selection descriptions that have been rejected - 'for the good of the species'. When we take a stance of either 'nature is nice and everything wants to work together', or 'nature is a cut-throat nasty place (and you might not like that, but thats the way it is)', we are resorting to sentamentalism. The intentions and morals of the entities involved, is neither here nor there. What matters is the adaptive mechanisms. Its nothing to do with selfishness vs altruism - even competition and cooperation might not be very useful terms. "Mutualism" - the living together of entities that gain mutual benefit from the association - has nothing to say about selfishness or altruism. The entities involved are just doing what they do. If only we could get past the emotive language we might be able to talk about higher-level selection without flipping-out.

So where are the tools with which we can begin to talk about mutualism and its role in evolutionary adaptation?

Fuzzy units-of-selection

The usual explanation for mutualist adaptations is to reduce the level of interactions to a finer level to show that 'in fact' each individual involved was acting in its own self-interest. As I have said - what else would you expect? So, rather than reducing macro-level adaptations to a micro-level explanation (as if that explained anything), I suggest that it might be more useful to talk about selection occuring (to greater or lesser degrees) at many levels simultaneously. Here's one approach - I focus on the fact that the units-of-selection in nature are pretty fuzzy: So, for example, the characteristics of individuals are strongly heritable and individuals are easily differentiated from other individuals (for the most part). Thus, the level of individual is a useful one is explaining adaptation. Another useful level is the gene. Genes are highly heritable and easily differentiated.

However, note that neither of these levels alone provides a full explanation. The complete set of characteristics that describes an individual is not perfectly heritable under sexual reproduction because subsets of genes are crossed-over. And, conversely, one gene is not completely differentiable from another - they are often tightly coupled within an individual. Put simply, genes are more likely to reproduce together if they come from the same individual than if they come from different individuals. Niether the gene level nor the individual level tells the whole story. On the one hand, as Dawkins will agree, you cant tell a complete story about the adaptation of individuals without mentioning genes. But on the other hand, you cant tell a complete story about the adaptation of genes without mentioning individuals. Neither level of description is 'the right level'.

So, there are many levels being acted on by selection, and all these levels are (potentially) valuable for describing the system. The usefulness of a level (the extent to which a level influences adaptation) is dependent on the coherence of components at that level. The interesting thing about the major transitions in natural evolution is that, one way or another, the coherence of the system at a higher level became dramatically increased. For example, when the DNA of one bacteria gets 'under the skin' of another bacteria (as in the formation of the eukaryotes) the coherence of the pair is dramatically increased. In other cases, the increase in coherence may be more subtle. For example, it may involve the behavioural maintenance of the group - that is, adaptation at the individual level produces behaviours that maintain the coherence of the group. Having been formed, the group is now a unit of selection and adaptation occurs at the group level.

Note that the individual level is still present, to some degree - adaptation at the individual level may still occur. But, to the extent that the coherence of the group is maintained, adaptation at the individual level is subsumed by adaptation at the group level. If we assume that variations are generaly reversible then, in some cases, an individual may arise that does not maintain the coherence of the group, and perhaps it may gain subsequent advantage. However, it is also possible to imagine that a group, by chance, may get itself into a part of variation space such that all individual variations that break the coherence of the group are more detrimental than advantageous. If this is the case then the coherence of the group will be further supported and 'solidified'. Steven Frank talks about "thresholds" in "mutual policing" - and I think this is where we are headed.

The fact of the matter is that mutualism is, at least sometimes, adaptive. Moreover, it sometimes has significant impact on the course of evolution, as cited above. My argument has been that this is because selection may have an effect on many levels (not just the individual or the gene). The strength of its influence on a group is related to the coherence of that group. If the coherence of the group becomes self-perpetuating then selection of at the group level will subsume selection at the individual level. In fact, as with the eukaryotes, it is no longer useful to talk about the original individuals - as Margulis says,  we have "individuality at a more complex level". Such a transition may, on rare occasions, bring a major transition in evolutionary history. But just as interesting, is the notion that more subtle groups may be having more subtle influence not just on rare occasions but in a widespread, even pandemic, sense.  Thus mutualism, far from being an insignificant curio, may be an important key mechanism in evolutionary adaptation.

Research directions

Ideally, we should be able to answer questions like: I am also interested in how can we use inspiration from these natural mechanisms to provide effective problem solving techniques. My masters dissertation explored several different features of symbiosis and group interaction in artificial evolution, (A study of the Effect of Group Formation on Evolutionary Search). Since then I have begun a more systematic decomposition of the elements involved.

My hunch is that the formation of mutually benefitial groups will be adaptively useful when the environment presents a problem that is 'partially decomposable'. That is, a problem with identifiable sub-parts, but where these sub-problems are not completely independent. In this case, the coupled structure of a problem will be reflected in the structure of coupling in the (eco)system that adapts to it. I have spent more than half of my research effort on trying to formalise what kind of coupling I might be talking about. The result of this is an abstract building-block problem which I call HIFF (hierarchical if-and-only-if) (Modeling Building-Block Interdependency), (Hierarchically-Consistent GA Test Problems), (C code for the HIFF test function). This problem has a hierarchical structure of coupled building-blocks. It makes a good test problem for regular GAs but, more importantly for me, there are variants of this problem that cannot be solved by the regular GA, but may, I suggest, be solved by a form of symbiotic algorithm.

Now I have begun to make modifications to the GA to address its inadequacies with respect to this class of problems. (Incremental Commitment in Genetic Algorithms) The important characterisation of this algorithm is that mating between two parents produces the combination of building-blocks they contain, as distinct from a 'bit of this one, bit of that one' that you get in normal recombination. This paper shows how individuals can be used to represent sub-solutions explicitly such that their combination provides whole-solutions.

In the meantime, I've done some (almost unrelated) excursions into how the formation of mutualist groups can have a shaping influence on evolution. My first paper illustrated how the formation of mutualist groups can guide genetic variation so as to enable the evolution of ultimately independent organisms that would otherwise be unobtainable.(How Symbiosis Can Guide Evolution), My second paper, with Torsten Reil, shows that this effect applies not just in genetically related organisms but may also occur from symbiosis between distinct species. (Mutualism, Parasitism and Evolutionary Adaptation) Also available in html.

The next, and critical, step in the research is to bring the group evaluation used in the symbiosis work of the last two papers together with the partial specification (incremental commitment) demonstrated in the GA work. I just figured out how to do this.  This will demonstrate a problem solving method utilising the evolution of groups and collective problem solving rather than individual problem solving. In addition, it will demonstrate the encapsulation of these groups into new individuals so that the process can recurse, making groups at increasing levels of complexity.

However, even when this works, it will be quite some way from a model of symbiosis in natural evolution. It wont describe any behavioural methods for group formation or self-sustaining groups, for example, since the required mechanisms are primitive operations in this algorithm. This reflects my computer science background, and, in fact, I'm not sure how to go about transforming the algorithm into a model that biologists might appreciate. However, in the meantime, it will provide an illustration of how hierarchical selection can be an effective adaptive mechanism - and this is likely to have something to say about the conditions under which symbiosis will be influential in natural evolution.

References

Maynard-Smith, JM & Szathmary, E, 1995, "The Major Transitions in Evolution", WH Freeman and Co.

Margulis L, 1992, Symbiosis in Cell Evolution: Microbial Communities in the Archean and Ptroterozoic Eons. 2d ed., W.H. Freeman, New York.

Merezhkovsky KS, 1909 "The Theory of Two Plasms as the Basis of Symbiogenesis, a New Study or the Origins of Organisms," Proceedings of the Studies of the Imperial Kazan University, Publishing Office of the Imperial University. (In Russian, see Khakhina 1992).